[CATEGORY IN INDEX AT STEIN-BRATEN.NET: OPENING LECTURES]
Beginning lecture for the world wide Agenda Key
Institutions Meeting of CHILDWATCH
International Research Network, 25-27 June 2005,
Hurdalsjöen Conference
Centre, Norway
Other-centred infants: Showing proto-care, even
altruism, by virtue of altercentric perception
subserved by mirror neurons
STEIN BRATEN
Dept of Sociology and Human Geography, University
of Oslo
Abstract.
Infants reciprocating caregiving and
toddlers affording
helping and altruistic behaviours invite the
question about the
foundations of such early prosocial behaviours.
In terms of the revealed
capacity for other-centered participation two
different replies are
offered, the first about nature, the second about
nurture: (i) the
altercentric capacity enables the childs'
empathic identification with
the patient's distress, evoking concern and
attempts to relieve the
patient of his distress; (ii) when the child is
the subject of
caregiving, altercentricity enables the child to
learn to afford care
from virtually participating in the caregiver's
activity, and which
invites circular re-enactment towards others felt
to be in need. Such
kind of cultural learning, however, may also
apply in some cases of
abuse, evoking vicious circles of re-enactment
later in life. In spite
of a gruesome background, however, episodic
evidence of altruism
afforded to one another by 3-year-old orphans
rescued from Nazi
concentration camp, as reported by Anna Freud,
attests to an innate
basis for altruism deeper than that of cultural
learning.
I thank the CWI organizing committee for the
invitation to give this
lecture to the participants of this Agenda Key
Institutions Meeting of
Childwatch International Research Network. In
view of your research on
childhood and children oriented towards to
improving their conditions
around the globe, it is an honour and a privilege
to have been asked
set the tone for the meeting' by reporting from
my own research on
preverbal intersubjectivity and new findings
pertinent to early
childhood research. My topic concerns proto-care
and circular
re-enactment by infants, moving with the (mouth)
movements of others by
virtue of what I have identified as
of infant psychology and neurosociology (Braten
1998, 2002, 2003, 2004).
I shall touch upon the foundations of
the most prominent in the intersection of brain
research and infant
research: Colwyn Trevarthen (1979, 1998). I shall
refer to a new
introduction to the seminal work on
by Daniel Stern (2000/2003), who is the most
prominent in the
intersection of infant research and clinical
psychology, and has just
published a new book in that intersection. And I
shall tell you about
the startling discovery of so-called
(eds.) 2002; Gallese & Ferrari in press) which
afford the likely
neurosocial support of what I have defined as
radical conception that runs counter to notions
of egocentricity in
traditional theories of child development and is
endorsed by the infant
and brain researchers named above. They are all
members of the Theory
Forum network on the foundations of (pre)verbal
intersubjectivity. We
convened with other members in a Theory Forum
symposium on new pertinent
findings in the Norwegian Academy of Science and
Letters last autumn
(3-5 October 2004), and which followed up another
symposium in the
Academy ten years previously, resulting in the
proceedings on
Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in
Early Ontogeny that I
edited for Cambridge University Press (1998).
That volume, in addition
to another volume in preparation with the title
On Being Moved: From
Mirror Neurons to Empathy (Braten (ed.) in
prep.), is the most imost
important reference work for what I am about to
tell you.
Neonatal imitation
Let me begin by introducing you to a video
recording of neonatal
imitation which another colleage of mine in the
Theory Forum network,
Giannis Kugiumutzakis, did at Crete in 1985.
When before that, in 1977,
Meltzoff and Moore published their paper on
neonatal imitation this came
as a chock to many of those who had been
socialized in the traditional
Piagetian and object-relations theories to view
infants as asocial or
egocentric. What is reported in this now
classical Science paper is how
each of the newborns, when exposed to the
lightened face of Andrew
Meltzoff exhibiting tongue protrusion, or lip
protrusion, or wide mouth
opening, took after his gesture in a manner that
could not be explained
away as a reflex act or a coincidence. These
newbornswere rather old,
however, -- actually between 12 and 22 days old.
What Kugiumutzakis did
a few years later was to invite such imitations
from much younger ones
-- between 20 and 45 minutes old -- whom you are
now about to see.
[Presentation of video records of newborns,
less than 60 minutes old,
imitating mouth and eyebrow movements, such as
tongue protrusion or wide
mouth opening (Recorded at Crete 1985 and
described by Kugiumutzakis
(1998:63-88), as well as in others of his
publications)]
And you can see from the newborns' intense
scrutiny of his whole face,
not just of the mouth or eyebrow used in the
movement, and the time they
need and the effort it takes to come up with a
semblant gesture, that
this is no reflex action. Take for example the
girl, twenty minutes old,
gazing intensely at his face as he does a wide
mouth-opening and then,
after a while, coming up with a semblant mouth
movement with an obvious
effort.
In one way, the newborn may be seen intuitively
to try to reach for the
centre of the other's mind; in another way by a
deliberate effort to
come up with a gestural match (cf. Kuguimutzakis
1998:80-81). Meltzoff &
Moore (1998:58) suggest that infants have a code
for interpreting that
the other is 'Like You and Liking You' -- in the double sense
of showing to (be) like the
other. In phylogenetic terms of survival: they
are making a case for
being picked up because of their being like (and
liking) the potential
caretaker. Being unable to physically cling, they
have to connect by
clinging'. This is suggested by the fact that it
is easer to elicit
neonatal imitation in the first hour after birth,
when survival would
have been at stake in the wilderness, than later
on.
When infants feed a companion and spectators are
dedicated to the
performer's success
We shall return to this video presentation. But
let me first show you
instances of pro-sociality or proto-care
exhibited by infants from
various cultures, who before the first year's
birthday feed or
spoon-feed their companion.
[Overhead presentaiton of photos of a
Norwegian boy (11 3/4 months),
spoonfeeding his elder sister (Braten 1996), of a
Yanomomi girl of abou
the same age, feeding her elder sister
(Eibl-Eibesfeldt 1979); and of an
Italian boy at a daycare centre feeding his girl
friend (photo by
Carolyn Pope Edwards)]
Here, for example, is a Norwegian boy, 11 3/4
months, reciprocating his
big sister's spoonfeeding (Braten 1996), an
Amazonas girl of about the
same age offering a morsel to her big sister
(Eibl-Eibesfeldt 1979) and
then, here you see a boy, almost a year older,
who feeds a cake to his
girl companion in an Italian daycare centre
(Carolyn Pope Edwards
brought this snapshot back from Italy when
returning to to my research
group in the Centre for Advanced Study (CAS) in
Oslo 1996-97). They all
afford instances of early pro-sociality and
proto-care. But what else do
you see in these pictures? Look closely..
Moving with the mouth movement of the other being
fed
Regard the mouth of the infant feeders; notice
how they are opening
their own mouth as their companions open the
mouth to receive the food
offered, and notice how the Yanomami girl
tightens her lips as her big
sister's mouth closes on the morsel. What you see
revealed here, like
what you yourself may unwittingly exhibit when
feeding a child or a
patient, is taking a virtual part in the
patient's intake of the food,
as if participating in the other's eating from
the other's stance, or
virtually helping the other to grasp by mouth the
food offered. These
are instances of what I have identified and
termed
(Braten 1997, 1998). As the very reverse of
perception of facing other
subjects from an ego-centric perspective,
other-centered participation
entails the empathic capacity to identify with
the other in a virtual
participant manner that evokes co-enactment or
shared experience as if
being in the other's bodily centre:
"Altercentric participation: ego's virtual
participation in Alter's
act as if ego were a co-author of the act or
being hand-guided from
Alter's stance. This is sometimes unwittingly
manifested overtly, for
example, when lifting one's leg when watching a
high jumper, or when
opening one's own mouth when putting a morsel
into another's mouth (and
differs from perspective-taking mediated by
conceptual representations
of others)" (Bråten, 2000:297-298).
In the glossary of his book on The Present Moment
in Psychotherapy and
Everyday Life, Daniel Stern offers this
definition:
"Altero-centered participation (Braten 1998b)
is the innate capacity
to experience, usually out of awareness, what
another is experiencing
[...] as if your center of orientation and
perspective were centered in
the other" (Stern 2004:241-242).
Stern sees such other-centred participation as
"the basic
intersubjective capacity that makes imitation,
sympathy, emotional
contagion, and identification possible" (p.242).
And what is more, when
you are not just watching the other about to
perform something, but
wishing for the other to succeed in whatever he
or she is doing, you
will tend to show by your own accompanying muscle
movements your virtual
participation in the other's effort as if you
were a co-author of the
other's doing. Actually, some of you have just
demonstrated this a few
moments ago.....
What some of lecture audiences do when watching a
video of neonal imitation
When you were the watching the newborn girl, 20
minutes old, preparing
for coming up with a wide mouth opening movement
resembling what
Kuguiumutzakis was doing with his mouth, some of
you in the audience
opened your own mouth -- not as imitation, but
slightly in advance of
the little girl -- as if to help her to achieve
this tremendous feat. I
took some photos of you, and here is a snapshot
of another lecture
audience exposed to the same video. As you can
see, while some of the
spectators are smiling, others open their own
mouth with a sincere
expression as if unwittingly trying to come to
virtual aid of what the
newborn girl is trying to do. And this is not
imitation. Being acutely
aware of what the little girl is trying to
prepare for; they open their
mouth before she manages to do so.
Adam Smith (1759) had noticed how spectators
watching a French line
dancer would sometimes wriggle and otherways move
their own bodies as if
helping the dancer to keep the balance as he
walked on the slack line.
He saw this as a manifestation of what he termed
term when considering the Greek roots of
suffering). About a hundred years later, Darwin
(XXXX.), in his work on
expression of emotions in animal and in man,
mentions that he has heard
of sport event spectators of high jumping who
move their own legs when
watching the high jumper take off, but he doubted
that girls would do
such a thing. Darwin was wrong. I have a video
(which I shall later show
you) illustrating how our Norwegian princess,
Märtha Louise, in the
spectator box at the summer Olympics 2000 in
Sidney, jumps high in the
air as her horse, ridden by an Englishman, is
about to cross the last
high obstacle.
So, what she was doing when watching what the
horse and rider was trying
to do, and what some of you were doing when
watching what the little
girl was trying to do, or what the feeder often
unwittingly does when
the patient prepares to mouth grasp the afforded
food, is to show by
your muscle activation and semblant part
movements or co-movements
(termed Mit-Bewegungen by Eibl-Eibeslfeldt
1997:???) that you take a
virtual part in what the other is trying to do,
as if sharing the bodily
centre of the other's muscular activity. This is
other-centred
partipation entailing altercentricity -- the very
reverse of egocentricity.
Mirror neurons system are the likely neurosocial
support of altercentric
participation
When introducing and illustrating altercentricity
in a CAS lecture in
The Norwegian Academy of Science and Letters
(March 1997), I made the
prediction that the neurosocial support of this
capacity would come to
be discovered:
"Now, if by way of experimental procedures,
the neural basis
supporting egocentric perception and the neural
basis sensitized to
support allocentric perception [subserved by
so-called
animals to retrieve stored food independent of
own body position] are
uncovered in humans, then I would expect that
neural systems, perhaps
even neurons, sensitized to realize altercentric
perception will be
uncovered in experiments designed to test and
disconfirm this
expectation." (reprinted in Braten 1998:122-123).
When making the above prediction I did not know
about the discovery of
so-called
in decentred adapted form afford the likely
support of such
other-centred participation (cf. Braten 2004). In
the autumn of 1997,
however, when completing my editing the volume on
Intersubjective
Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny, I
learnt to my delight of
the original macaque experiment conducted by
Rizzolatti and co-workers,
reported by Di Pellegrino et al. (1992), and
managed in time to include
in that volume (Braten (ed.) 1998:120-122) a
portrayal of that
experiment. In this experiment the macaque
monkey, allowing for
electronic recording of degrees of disharge of
pre-motor nerve cells in
the monkey's parietal lobe, is watching the
experimenter grasp a morsel
from a board, and then given the opportunity to
grasp such a morsel from
the board. In both cases there is a significant
premotor cell activation
and discharge of what later came to be termed
for the fact that they fire both when the macaque
is doing the grasping
and when the macaque is watching another's
grasping.
There is even a differential discharge that
varies with the intent,
recently revealed in macaque monkey experiments:
When the experimenter
grasp a morsel with the intent til eat it, there
will be a strong
discharge in the watcher, while if it is grasped
in order to be thrown
in a bucket, the mirror neurons discharge in the
watching macaque is
weaker. Fogassi et al. (2005:662-667 ) have
reported this in an April
issue of Science this year. So, there is link
between resonating to a
specific act, and which varies according to the
action in which that act
is embedded, i.e. a link between mirror resonance
of the act and the
intention: there is stronger mirror resonance
elicited by watching
grasping in order to eat that which is grasped
than by watching grasping
in order to throw away that which is grasped.
Already in 1998, Rizzolatti and Arbib in their
Trends in Neuroscience
article on Language within our grasp, indicate
the location of mirror
neurons in the chimpanzze brain and of a mirror
neurons system in the
prefrontal cortex of the human brain. They
suggested that such a system
not just subserves action understanding, but may
have played a role in
the phylogeny of language, supporting intention
understanding in the
first primitive dialogues. This we have followed
up two years later in a
conference on mirror neurons and the evolution of
brain and language,
organized by Maxim Stamenov and one of
Rizzolatti's co-discoverers,
Vittorio Gallese (cf. Stamenov & Gallese 2002).
Here, and in a
commentary to the anthropologist Dean Falk's
(2004) article last autumn
on Prelinguistic evolution in early hominins, I
have proposed that the
efficient speech perception that may be observed
in early ontogeny may
have been subserved by a phylogenetically
afforded and adapted resonant
mirror system, decentred in phylogeny to subserve
(m)other-centred
participation by hominin infants. Such an evolved
decentred capacity for
learning by altercentric perception to cope and
take care would have
overcome and compensated (at least before the
(Homo Erectus ?) invention
of baby slings) for the loss of the instructive
and protective advantage
enjoyed by back-clinging offsprings of other
primates (Braten
2002:289-290; 2004:508-509).
Perceptual mirror reversal found to be difficult
in autism
Such a phylogenetic adaptation of the mirror
neurons system entails that
when the infant is watching and imitating the
performing other
face-to-face, a perceptual mirror reversal is
occurring.
While ordinary children in virtue of altercentric
perception can do what
the other is doing when seen face-to-face,
children with autism who
understand and comply with the invitation
example, when the model is raising his arms, the
subject with autism may
compare the inside of the model's hands with own
hands and, then, raise
his own hands with the palms inwards (cf. Fig.
5.4 in Braten's chapter
and the chapter by Whiten & Brown in Braten (ed.)
1998: 260-282).
Circular re-enactment from learning by
other-centred participation
As the very reverse of perception of facing
subjects from an ego-centric
perspective, other- centered participation
entails the empathic capacity
to identify with the other in a virtual
participant manner that evokes
co-enactment or shared experience as if being in
the other's bodily
centre. You can understand how this may invite in
children a general
proclivity towards prosocial and even altruistic
behaviour. Here is the
proposition:
(i) By virtue of the innate capacity for
other-centered participation
in the patient's distress or felt need as if
experiencing that from the
patient's center, there is a natural proclivity
in the child to feel
concern and sometimes attempt to help the
patient, perhaps even at own
expence, if situational and motoric resources
permit.
If helping occurs at own expence, then this would
per definition entail
altruism. Does this apply to the previous
examples of infants feeding
other? Not quite, and only if those infants would
have preferred to
reserve the food afforded for themselves. In the
case of the Norwegian
boy, that certainly did not apply. True, he
reciprocated his sister's
spoonfeeding, but only until the sweet desert;
that he kept to himself;
no more sharing then...
Circular re-enactment of caregiving from
e-motional memory
From previously being spoon-fed by his
caregivers, however, he had
learnt to (take delight) in spoon-feeding others
in return, and to do so
before his first birthday. Such an impressive
early feat of cultural
learning entails that nature has been at play: an
innate capacity for
imitative learning even of care-giving, and which
now permits
specifications in terms of other-centred
participation:
(ii) Caregiving situations, which may appear to
be unilateral
activities, should be re-defined to be seen at
the reciprocal activities
entailed in virtue of the infant's taking a
virtual part in what the
caregiver does, and thereby learns from
alter-centric participation in
that very caregiving.
I shall now take a step further and offer an
account of how the
altercentric capacity invites in the child as a
subject of care or abuse
a mode of imitative learning which creates
virtuous and vicious circles
of re-enactment. But first some definitions of
pertinent terms are needed:
Felt immediacy: the mode of directly perceiving
own or others' body
movements and orientation in presentational
immediacy, in
contradistinction to experience in conceptual and
re-presentational mediacy.
Vitality Contour: term introduced by Daniel Stern
for the temporal
contour of feeling flow patterns with a
characteristic intensity
time-course of vitality affects reflecting the
manner in which an
activity has been enacted and the feeling that
directs the enactment.
Learning by altercentric participation:
imitational learning by Ego's
virtual participation in Alter's act in felt
immediacy which
(1) evokes sensori-motor engagement in Alter's
movements in a
participatory sense involving virtual
co-enactment of Alter's movements
as if Ego were hand-guided and a co-author of
Alter's act,
(2) giving rise to shared temporal vitality
(affects) contours,
reflecting the manner in which the enactment is
felt to be virtually
co-enacted and the feeling that directs the
co-enactment,
(3) enabling circular re-enactment from
e-motional memory of such
virtual co-enactments,
(4) which in face-to-face situation entails
mirror reversal of Alter's
enactment -- from being other-centred perceived
to being self-centred
executed as circular re-enactment.
Such learning entail a kind of procedural memory
or, as I would specify
it, an e-motional memory. By "e-motional memory"
I mean here the
affective remembrance -- which is not conceptual
and may not be
conscious -- of virtually moving with Alter's
movements leaving Ego with
a characteristic vitality contour and procedural
memory of the virtual
co-enactment which may be evoked for re-enactment
in similar situations.
The composite term "e-motional" combines the folk
sense of being
and the root sense
In an environment affording care, the infant gets
recurrent
opportunities to not just be subjected to care
but to feel to be
virtually co-enacting such caregiving, inviting
circular re-enactment
from e-motional memory of such caregiving if and
when others in need or
distress reactivate in the child feelings
semblant of the form of bodily
self-feelings evoked in situations in which the
infant has experienced
caregiving, and hence activating circular
re-enactment of care.
Then others in need or distress may invite caring
efforts resembling the
caring afforded by others earlier in infancy from
e-motional memory of
having virtually participated in that caregiving.
We may also, in line
with Fogel (2004), use the term participative
memory.
(iii) The kind of caretaking frequently
experienced by the infant in
virtue of alter-centric participation provides a
basis for circular
re-enactment of that kind of caretaking towards
other children in need
or distress.
This fits with studies revealing how the quality
of the caregiving
background appears to play a role in children's
reaction towards others
in need: Those from a nurturant and caring
background are most likely to
help and offer comfort to other children in need
or distress (Berk 1994;
Zahn-Waxler et al. 1979). Thus, altercentric
participation is at play in
a twofold way here: first, by the part it plays
in learning from
caregivers who have left the child with an
e-motional or participatory
memory of caregiving; second, by the way in which
altercentric
participation may be elicited by others in need
or distress, and thereby
activating circular re-enactment of caregiving
offered to them.
Thus, sensitive caretaking frequently experienced
by the infant in the
reciprocal mode of felt immediacy may come to
provide a basis for
circular re-enactment of semblant kinds of
caretaking towards other
children in need or distress.
Child abuse inviting circular re-enactment of
abuse
But caretaking experiences need of course not
only be experiences of
caring, comfort and holding (in Winnicott's
sense). Parents, caretakers
and others may be guilty of various forms of
abuse. And if the above
applies, then we should also expect that
experiences of abuse and
rejection in caretaking may come to invite
vicious circles of
re-enactment. That is implied by proposition
(iii).
In the way that sensitive caregiving invites
circular re-enactment then
we should also expect that experiences of abuse
may come to invite
circles of re-enactment:
(iv) Circular re-enactment of abuse somehow
entails that the child
victim has been compelled not just to suffer the
victim part, but to
feel to participate in the abusive movements,
sharing the vitality
contours reflecting the manner of abuse and the
feelings that direct the
abuse. In virtue of such altercentric
participation the victim may come
to experience engagement in the bodily motions
and feelings of the
abuser, not just own suffering. That leaves the
victim with a compelling
bodily and emotional remembrance that increases
the likelihood of
circular re-enactment of abuse in peer relations
or towards younger
children later in ontogeny from e-motional memory
of having virtually
participated in actual alter's abuse, while
suffered by the victim's
bodily ego. (END NOTE)
However, if the victim is incapable of
altercentric participation in the
abuser's activity, or defence mechanisms prevent
any sharing of vitality
contours with the abuser, reflecting the manner
of abuse and the
feelings that direct the abuse, then we should
not expect the victim to
be able to reverse positions and become an abuser
in relations to
others. Defence mechanisms or biological
impairments may prevent
altercentric participation in the abuser's
activity from the abuser's
stance. If not, there is the risk of circular
re-enactment of abuse
towards others in the course of ontogeny.
Classical theories of learning cannot be used to
account for this; only
how to learn to become and remain a victim from
being abused. In his
article in Forum der Psychoanalyse, Dornes
(2002:303-331) points to
links between my account of circular re-enactment
of abuse and the
psychoanalytic notions of
the introject". He stresses, however, that my
account implies a sort of
"identification" at a subsymbolic and body-near
level entailing no
symbolic representations:
"[Braten's] theory follows the intuition of
Freud (1920) that
compulsive repetition ("Wiederholungszwang") is a
biologically founded
phenomenon, albeit here not anchored in the death
instinct, but in a
form of resonance theory" (Dornes 2002:319n).
Thus, this means virtual participation in a more
narrow sense,
participation in the sense of felt immediacy in
the abuser's movements
as if being a co-author, and leaving the victim
with a bodily, not
conceptual, remembrance that call upon circular
re-enactment. And, as
Dornes makes clear, I account for the
re-enactment of abuse in terms of
the very same life-giving mechanism operating in
children's proto-care
and in their re-enacting the caregiving they have
experienced.
Empirical support: abused toddlers are more
likely to become abusive
than other toddlers
Thus, prior to defence mechanisms setting in, the
abused child is not
just a victim of the abuse, but virtually takes a
part in the abusive
and hurtful event as a co-enactor of the abuse,
inviting as one of
several paths an increased likelihood of circular
re-enactment of
abusive behaviour towards other potential
victims.
The above implies that children who have
experienced caretaking or
parenting in a harsh, punitive, neglecting or
abusive manner should be
more likely to respond with fear, anger, or even
attack peers or younger
children in distress, as compared to responses by
children with a
different experiential background. Empirical
studies point in this
direction. For example, observing abused toddlers
abusing other infants
George and Main (1985) indicate a vicious circle
in the early impact of
the quality of the caretaking background.
Severely abused toddlers have
been observed at a day-care centre to react
fearfully or aggressive
towards other children in distress, and by the
second year of their life
to re-enact the abusive behaviour of their
parents. Some of the toddlers
found to having been abused were never observed
to express obvious
concern for another child in distress. Sometimes,
they even tormented
the other child until it began crying and then,
while smiling,
mechanically patted or attempted to quiet the
crying child (Harris 1989;
George and Main 1985).
There is thus a double vicious circle in the
tragedy of child victims of
abuse. Not only are they deprived of full
emotional holding quality in
their own life. By virtue of circular
re-enactment from e-motional
memory of abuse, some of them may even later in
ontogeny be driven to
deprive others of that same quality of life (END
NOTE).
Again, as in the case of circular re-enactment of
care, no conceptual or
verbal "memory" need be involved for experiences
of abuse in felt
immediacy to give rise to re-enactment. Were a
conceptual or verbal
memory to be at play, the likelihood of circular
re-enactment from
e-motiional memory of abuse could be expected to
be reduced. Indeed, men
and women who have been subjected to incest and
abuse in their infancy
or early childhood may first come to realize that
they may have been
victims when a crisis breaks out in adult years.
But while the
experience of abuse is not re-presented in virtue
of any conceptual
memory, the child is certainly affected in the
most profound way. That
is why the composite term e-motional "memory" is
useful to denote the
affective experience and remembrance of moving
with the other's motions
that afford the infant the feeling of
participating in the movement and
accompanying emotions. Different from
higher-order conceptual memory,
this kind of "e-motional memory" will be
ineffaceably affected by
abusive motions felt to be co-enacted, and
increase the likelihood of
circular re-enactment later in ontogeny of the
previously felt
co-enacted movements.
When orphan victims, 3 years old, exibit altruism
in relation to one
another (NOTE)
Both human nature and social nurture have been
shown to be at play in
the above domains.
If altruism and protocare in young children were
to be the product of
cultural learning only, then we should expect
that three-year old
children, rescued from Nazi concentration camps
and whose parents were
killed in the gas chambers, would be incapable to
afford care and show
concern for others. But that is clearly not the
case as reported by Anna
Freud and Sophie Dann (1951). They studied six
German-Jewish orphans,
three boy victims and three girl victims, rescued
in 1945 from the the
concentration camp in Terezin, where three of
them had been since they
were about 6 months, and the others since they
were 12 months old or
younger. Their parents were deported and killed
soon after their birth,
and they arrived in the concentration camp when
they were 6 months old
and some approachiing 12 months. All of them were
deprived from the
beginning of any
outside a camp or big institution (p.167). Here
they were looked after
by the inmates of the ward for motherless
children, feeding them as well
as possible but unable to attend to any of their
other needs, and
certainly not playing with them (p.167-168n). On
October 1945 they
arrived, via a Czech Castle where they given
special care and lavishly
fed, in Bulldogs Bank in UK.
As could have been expected, upon arrival in
Bulldogs Bank the children
were extremely hostile towards the adults and the
environment afforded
them. They destroyed all toys (had never been
engaged in playing with
toys) and damaged much of the interior
environment. Towards the staff
they behaved with active hostility, hitting,
biting, spitting, shouting
and screaming, and at other times with cool
indifference except when
they had to turn to an adult to satisfy some
need; when satisfied the
adult was again treated as beeing non-existent
(p.168).
Upon arrival on October 1945 the two youngest of
them, Miriam and Peter,
were about 3 years old, the oldest, John, 3 years
and 10 months, and in
between these three others who were three and a
half year old, Ruth,
Paul and Leah, who was delayed for six weeks due
to a ringworm
infection. When she arrived, the five other
children had accommodated
themselves to a certain extent to the new
surroundings, picked up some
English terms which they sometimes could use in
contact with the staff.
When, however, Leah arrived, with no special
qualities inviting a
special status, except for her being a newcomer,
all the five others
behaved once more as if they were all newcomers
like her, reverting to
German, "shouted and screamed, and were again out
of control." (Freud
(with Dann) 1973:173))
This is indicative of how one of the children
could be in the center of
the others' empathic identification, manifested
by their altered
behaviour. As Anna Freud points out, they
identified with Leah, and as I
would put it, by reverting to the behaviour and
language of Leah, the
other orphans appear to manifest their
other-centred participation in
her doings. And as Leah became more adjusted to
the new environment, so
did the others accommodate, returning now to
their previous slightly
adapted behaviour, including their recent
adoption of English terms.
And all the time, the orphans showed themselves
to be extremely
considerate of one another's feelings, showed
concern for one another
and affording care, often at own expence. Upon
arrival in Bulldogs Bank,
they did not know how to play with toys, but when
learning, they
silently assisted one another or admired one
another's productions when
for example building something.
Perhaps most impressive, in view of their
gruesome and depriving
backgrounds, was they way they behaved towards
one another at mealtimes:
handing food to the companion was more important
than having food
oneself (p.174). Here are two telling examples,
occurring respectively
in November and December after their arrival in
October:
"John [3 years 11 months] cries when there
is no cake left for a
second helping for him. Ruth [3 years 7 months]
and Miriam [3 years 3
months] offer him what is left of their portions.
While John eats their
pieces of cake, they pet him and comment
contently on what they have
given him."
"Paul [3 years and 7 month] has a plate full
of cake crumbs. When he
begins to eat them, the other children want them
too. Paul give the
biggest crumbs to Miriam, the three middle-sized
one to the other
children, and eats the smallest one for himself"
(Freud (with Dann)
1973:175)
Even though Paul in the latter episode has an
ambivalent attitude
towards food (p.201), both of these episodes may
be seen to demonstrate
altruistic behaviour. In the first episode, the
two girls act in an
altruistic manner, giving John their piece of
cake at their own expence.
Their content and commenting behaviour suggests
their taking delight in
his eating. Their empathic identification is
indicative of othercentered
participation which probably underlies and gives
rise their altruistic act.
Thus, here we see telling examples of the way in
which the apparent
innate capacity for othercentered participation,
and which plays a part
in altruism, may break through and make itself
felt even against the
most gruesome and depriving backgrounds. When
Paul, about to eat, shares
his plate full of cake crumbs with the other
children, keeping the
smallest crumb for himself", and when Ruth and
Miriam give crying John
their own pieces of cake, petting him and
commenting contently as he
helps himself, these are beautiful examples of
altruism in its bright
light against the dark and depriving background
of these orphans.
End Note
It need not come to circular re-enactment of
abuse, however; several
other paths are open to the victim. One such
alternative path is to
disengage from the body subjected to abuse, or to
divorce the bodily ego
from the virtual alter, each running their
separate course. Circular
re-enactment of abuse may be also be prevented if
the previous victim's
capacity for altercentric participation is not
"turned off" in relation
to other potential victims, unless pain-seeking
has become a motivating
force.
References
Braten, S. (1996) Infants demonstrate that
care-giving is reciprocal.
Centre for Advanced Study Newsletter no.2
(November), p. 2.
Braten, S. (Ed. 1998) Intersubjective
Communication and Emotion in Early
Ontogeny. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Braten, S. (1998a) Infant learning by
altercentric participation: the
reverse of egocentric observation in autism. In
S. Bråten (Ed.)
Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in
Early Ontogeny, (pp. 105-
124). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Braten, S. (1998b) Intersubjective communion and
understanding:
development and perturbation. In S. Bråten (Ed.)
Intersubjective
Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny, (pp.
272-382). Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Braten, S. (1998c) Kommunikasjon og samspill -
fra fødsel til alderdom
(Communication and Interplay from Birth to Old
Age). Oslo:
Tano-Aschehoug (Danish edition: Dafolo Forlag
1999)..
Braten, S. (2002) Altercentric perception by
infants and adults in
dialogue. In M. Stamenov & V. Gallese(Eds.)
Mirror neurons and the
evolution of brain and language, (pp. 273-294),
Amsterdam/Philadelphia:
John Benjamins Publ Co.
Braten, S. (2003) Participant perception of
others' acts: Virtual
otherness in infants and adults. Culture &
Psychology 9 (3): 261-76.
Braten, S. (2004) The hominin infant decentration
hypothesis: Mirror
neurons system adapted to subserve mother-centred
participatio.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (4): 508-509.
Braten, S. & C. Trevarthen (1994) Beginnings of
cultural learning. Talk
at the ZiF symposium on The Formative process of
society, Bielefeld
17-19 Nov 1994. In: S.Braten: Modellmakt og
altersentriske spedbarn.
Essays on Dialogue in Infant & Adult.(pp.
213-218) Bergen: Sigma 2000.
Dornes, M. (2002) Der virtuelle Andere. Aspekte
vorsprachlicher
Intersubjektivität. Forum der Psychoanalyse, 18,
303-331.
Eibl-Eibesfeldt, I. (1997) Die Biologie des
menschlichen Verhaltens.
Weyarn: Seehamer Verlag.
Fogassi, L. et al. (2005) Parietal Lobe: From
Action Undestanding to
Intention Understanding.Science vol. 308 29 April
2005: 662-667.
Fogel, A. (2004) Remembering Infancy: Accessing
our Earliest
Experiences. In G.Bremner & A. Slater
(Eds.):Theories of Infant
Development, Cambridge: Blackwell: 204-230.
Freud, Anna (with Sophie Dann) (1951/1973) An
Experiment in Group
Upbringing. The PsychoanalyticStudy of the Child
6:127-168 (reprinted in
The Writings of Anna Freud, Vol. IV. New York:
International
Universities Press 1973:163-229).
Freud, S. (1920) Beyond the Pleasure Principle..
In J. Strachey (Ed.;
Transl.). The Standard edition of the complete
psychological works of
Sigmund Freud (Vol. 18, pp. 7-64). London:
Hogarth.
George, C. & M. Main (1979) Social interaction of
young abused children:
Approach, avoidance and aggression. Child
Development, 50, 306-318.
Harris, P.L. (1989) Children and Emotion. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Kugiumutzakis, G. (1998) Neonatal imitation in
the intersubjective
companion space. In S. Braten (Ed.)
Intersubjective Communication and
Emotion in Early Ontogeny, (pp. 63-88).
Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Meltzoff, A.N. & Moore, M.K. (1998) Infant
intersubjectivity: broading
the dialogue to include imitation, identity and
intention. In S. Braten
(Ed.) Intersubjective Communication and Emotion
in Early Ontogeny (pp.
47-62). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rizzolatti, G. & M. Arbib (1998) Language within
our grasp. Trends in
Neurosciences 21 (5) 188-193.
Rizzolatti, G., Fograssi, L. & Gallese, V. (2000)
Cortical mechanisms
subserving object grasping and action
recognition. In M.S. Gazzaniga
(Ed.) The New Cognitive Neurosciences, (pp.
539-552). Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press/Bradford.
Stamenov, M. & V. Gallese (Eds. 2002) Mirror
Neurons and the Evolution
of Brain and Language. Amsterdam/Philadelphia.
Stern, D.N. (1999) Vitality Contours: The
temporal contour of feeling as
a basis unit for constructing theinfant's social
experience, in P.
Rochat (Ed.) Early Social Cognition, (pp. 67-80).
London/Mahwah, N.J.:
Lawrence Erlbaum.
Stern, D.N. (2000) Introduction to the paperback
edition, in D.N. Stern,
The Interpersonal World of the Infant
(pp.xi-xxxix). New York: Basic Books.
Trevarthen, C. (1979) Communication and
cooperation in early infancy: A
description of primary intersubjectivity, in M.M.
Bullowa (Ed.) Before
Speech (pp.321-347). New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Trevarthen, C. (1986) Development of
intersubjective motor control in
infants. In M.G. Wade & H.T. A.Whiting (Eds:)
Motor Development in
Children (pp. 209-61). Dordrecht: Martinus
Nijhoff.
Trevarthen, C. (1992) An infant's motive for
speaking and thinking in
the culture. In A.H. Wold (Ed.) The Dialogical
Alternative, (pp.
99-137). Oslo: Scandinavian University Press /
Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Trevarthen, C. (1993) The self born in
intersubjectivity. In U. Neisser
(Ed.) The Perceived Self (pp.121- 173). New York:
Cambridge University
Press.
Trevarthen, C. (1998) The concept and foundations
of infant
intersubjectivity, in: S. Braten (Ed.)
Intersubjective Communication and
Emotion in Early Ontogeny, (pp. 15-46).
Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Trevarthen, C. & Hubley, P. (1978) Secondary
intersubjectivity. In A.
Lock (Ed.): Action, Gesture, and Symbol,
(pp.183-229). London: Academic
Press.
Whiten, A. & Brown, J. (1998) Imitation and the
reading of other minds.
In S. Braten (Ed.) Intersubjective Communication
and Emotion in Early
Ontogeny, (pp. 260-282). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Winnicott, D. (1953) Transitional objects and
transitional phenomena.
Int. J. Psychoanalysis, 59, pp.89- 97.
Winnicott, D. (1986) Home is where we start from.
Hammondsworth: Penguin.
TO SEE THE INDEX OF TEXTS IN THIS SITE, CLICK HERE